Divine Sovereignty and Human Responsibility

Introduction

The Bible portrays God as having and exercising sovereign control over all things, even the free acts of men, yet man is held morally responsible for their sinfulness. If God determines human actions, how are humans held morally responsible for them? How can he place blame when no one can alter his plan made from eternity past? Must people simply accept the biblical claim that God is absolutely sovereign and man is morally culpable, even if it cannot be explained how the two concepts can both be true?1 Romans 9:19 raises the question: “Why does he still find fault, for who can resist his will?”2 The answer: “Who are you, O man, to answer back to God? Will what is molded say to its molder, ‘Why have you made me like this?’ Has the potter no right over the clay, to make out of the same lump one vessel for honorable use and another for dishonorable use?” Does this mean the truths of divine sovereignty and human responsibility are irreconcilable? This is not necessarily the point of Paul’s statement. The answer provided in Romans 9:20–24 assumes the questioner is accusing God of injustice—that God rules unfairly over his creation. Is there an answer for someone who reverently acknowledges God’s sovereign control and humbly seeks to understand and submit to God’s ways? The solution presented in this paper argues that it is possible to understand how man is culpable for his actions even if every single action has been decreed by the sovereign hand of God.

The thesis to be argued in this paper is that God predetermines all things, including sin, yet mankind is held morally responsible since they choose sin freely and are creatures answerable to their creator.3 The goal is not to argue for God’s sovereignty and human responsibility as distinct principles, affirming both and letting the tension lie. Instead the goal is to analyze the relationship between the two principles and propose a system that accounts for both truth claims without logical contradiction or antinomy. While divine responsibility is not the main focus of this paper, it is briefly discussed as it relates to human responsibility.

Limiting the Scope

In this paper only proposals under a Calvinistic theological system will be considered when harmonizing the doctrines of divine sovereignty and human responsibility. This excludes limited-sovereignty models such as the free-will defense or middle-knowledge theory.4 The free-will defense rests on the notion that God limited himself in order to create creatures that were autonomous, exercising “true” (contra-causal) freedom, even if that leads to events that God does not desire to take place.5 The middle-knowledge theory posits God faced with all the possible worlds where autonomous creatures make “truly free” (contra-causal) choices and God selects the best world that is closest to or fits his purposes.6 In both systems, human freedom necessarily limits God and (in a sense) makes the creature dictate the Creator.7 They are ruled out as options because such a notion cannot be reconciled with Scripture. The Bible affirms the independence of God. “Whatever the LORD pleases, he does, in heaven and on earth, in the seas and all deeps” (Ps 135:6). “The LORD brings the counsel of the nations to nothing; he frustrates the plans of the peoples. The counsel of the LORD stands forever, the plans of his heart to all generations” (Ps 33:10–11).8

Formalizing the Problem

The tension between divine sovereignty and human responsibility is a formidable problem. A. W. Pink refers to it as the Gordian knot of theology.9 As previously mentioned, certain theological systems deny God’s absolute sovereignty over all things or propose that he sovereignly gives man the ability or freedom to override his complete control. This is because, if God is absolutely sovereign, they cannot escape the following syllogism:

Premise 1: Nothing comes to pass outside of God’s sovereign decree.
Premise 2: Sin exists, and man is sinful.
Corollary: Sin and sinful man are part of God’s decree.
Conclusion: God is morally responsible for sin and man’s sinfulness, not man.

The conclusion is rightly denied by Christian thinkers. However, this is often done by limiting divine sovereignty (tantamount to denying the first premise) or by denying that God decreed sin, but instead decreed free creatures (i.e., denying the corollary). This is done in to vindicate God’s responsibility for sin and impugn man. What will be shown is that the two premises and the corollary are in fact true, but that the conclusion does not follow. A successful argument must affirm the premises and corollary, yet account for man’s responsibility while denying God as the author of sin.

A brief defense of the syllogism is offered here to highlight the tensions before a solution is proposed and defended.

First Premise: Nothing Comes to Pass Outside of God’s Decree

The premise that nothing comes to pass outside of God’s decree must be affirmed. The Bible is clear in passages such as Ephesians 1:11 which state that God “works all things according to the counsel of his will” (cf. Rom 8:28). Even the very details of a person’s life are predetermined by God (Ps 139:16).

Second Premise: Sin Exists, and Man is Sinful

The premise that sin exists and man is sinful must be affirmed as Scripture has much to say on the subject. Paul demonstrates in Romans 1–3 that all humanity (both Jew and Greek) are under sin (Rom 3:9). Because of the fall, “death spread to all men because all sinned” (Rom 5:12).

Corollary: God Decreed Sin and Man’s Sinfulness

If God decrees whatever comes to pass then he has necessarily decreed sin and man’s sinfulness. A biblical example will suffice. The crucifixion took place according to the predetermined plan of God (Acts 2:23). The sinful actions of Herod, Pontius Pilate, the Gentiles, and the people of Israel were predetermined by God and were carried out according to his purpose (Acts 4:27–28). The corollary, therefore, must be affirmed as both necessary and explicitly taught in Scripture.

Conclusion: God is Morally Responsible for Sin and Man’s Sinfulness, Not Man

The conclusion that God is morally responsible for sin and man’s sinfulness must be denied since it cannot be reconciled with the Scriptures nor the nature of God (Matt 5:48; Jas 1:13). Using salvation as an example, the Bible is clear that man is solely responsible for the sin of unbelief and God is solely responsible for man’s belief. Being responsible for their sin, unbelievers are condemned for it (John 3:18), whereas believers have no basis for boasting (1 Cor 1:29) since they believe because they have been born from above (John 3:3). The tension is most notable here—the unbeliever is responsible for his unbelief, and yet the believer is not responsible for his belief. The question that remains to be addressed is: how can God be praised for the good man does and not be responsible for the evil man commits when he has decreed everything that comes to pass?

There are many other examples where Scripture affirms human responsibility for sin under the sovereign plan of God. Genesis 50:20 describes the evil intent of Joseph’s brothers and God’s good intent in sending Joseph to Egypt as a slave. Isaiah 10:5–15 describes God using the king of Assyria as his tool to punish Israel, at the same time the king of Assyria is wicked in his heart and is punished by God. Proverbs 16:4–5 affirms that God has made everything for its purpose (including the wicked) and that the wicked are still responsible for their wickedness and will not go unpunished (cf. 1 Pet 2:7–8). Luke 22:22 describes the betrayal of Jesus that was predetermined by God, yet Judas is still responsible for the act of betrayal. Acts 4:27–28 affirms that the crucifixion took place according to God’s decree, yet the wicked men involved are responsible and are judged according to their actions (cf. Acts 2:23). One of the clearest passages on divine sovereignty and human responsibility is found in Romans 9 which affirms that God has created vessels of wrath and vessels of mercy (Rom 9:22–23), yet man is still answerable to God (Rom 9:19–20). The remainder of this paper addresses the reconciliation of these seemingly irreconcilable truths.

Definitions

Before presenting a solution, a number of theological concepts must be understood or else the argument is framed on false suppositions. Too often philosophical presuppositions dictate the solution and loose the argument from the moorings of Scripture. The other approach to avoid is one that rightly affirms divine sovereignty and human responsibility, yet does not attempt to systematize relevant texts and instead leaves those concepts in tension. The goal, therefore, is to avoid both of these approaches and construct a sound biblical and philosophical reconciliation between divine sovereignty and human responsibility.

The nature of God’s decree, responsibility, ability, freedom, determinism, and providence are all important to understand when discussing a solution to the relationship between divine sovereignty and human responsibility.10 These concepts must be understood correctly to address the culpability—both human and divine—in a world sovereignly ruled by God.

Determinism

Determinism is the “general philosophical thesis which states that for everything that ever happens there are conditions such that, given them, nothing else could happen.”11 An indeterminist would deny that preconditions are sufficient to determine that a person would choose one thing over another.12 The Bible clearly portrays human history as determined by God, “Have you not heard that I determined it long ago? I planned from days of old what now I bring to pass” (Isa 37:26). The events of the past, present, and future are made certain because they are predetermined by God.

“Remember the former things of old;
for I am God, and there is no other;
   I am God, and there is none like me,
declaring the end from the beginning
   and from ancient times things not yet done,
saying, ‘My counsel shall stand,
   and I will accomplish all my purpose.’” (Isaiah 46:9–10)13

A common misconception of the deterministic position is that it amounts to fatalism. Fatalism claims that there is an “inherent necessity in the way things are so that they could not be any other way.”14 It claims that God could not have created the world any other way; there is no other conceivable world that God could have created. Fatalism must be denied as God did not create this world from necessity, and he could have created another world if he had desired to do so.

Another common misconception is that man is reduced to a robot—a mechanical thing rather than a real person.15 In this world of robots, God is seen as judging and punishing man for things that God himself is responsible for. This is an obvious misrepresentation of Scripture’s teachings. Man is capable of love and intimacy with God and is given dominion over creation. God has sent his only Son to die for mankind, rescuing them from corruption so that they may enjoy eternal fellowship with him. This certainly does not portray people as simply robots. At the same time, man is still under the sovereign rule of God. Why does God lavish such attention and love upon man who is under his complete control? God is concerned about glorifying himself, and man serves him in that purpose. This fact conflicts with the modern view of absolute human autonomy. Those who believe in Scripture must be willing to humble themselves and accept their creatureliness—that they were made by, and for, their creator (Ps 8:4; Col 1:16).

Responsibility

In philosophy, responsibility is defined as “the notion that a person is answerable for his actions and so is a proper subject for praise or blame.”16 Scripturally, man is clearly answerable for his actions before God. This is a consequence of God’s supreme authority over mankind and his role as judge of human conduct.17 God has created man in his image (Gen 1:27–28) and commands him to “be holy, for I am holy” (Lev 11:44; cf. 19:2; Matt 5:48; 1 Peter 1:15–16). Man then is responsible to live according to God’s holy standards and is held responsible for every word, thought, and deed; whether they be acts of commission or acts of omission (Jas 4:17).18 In this sense of responsibility—the creature under the creator—man is always and totally responsible. This sense of responsibility and the creator-creature distinction must be at the fore of any biblical discussion on the nature of divine sovereignty and human responsibility. As creatures of God, man’s foremost responsibility is to recognize his creatureliness and glorify his Creator.19

The biblical understanding of human responsibility toward God is oftentimes diminished by the view that man is only responsible for what he freely chooses. An even more nuanced view of responsibility includes not only actions due to free choice but also consequences due to negligence. In other words, responsibility is tied to the results of man’s actions but not entirely to the results of man’s own decisions.20 That is, man is liable for his actions and lack thereof.21 Responsibility as liability is usually understood to be measured in degrees of guilt. The modern law code is an example of this with murder being measured in degrees, or manslaughter being voluntary or involuntary. This kind of responsibility is not only predicated on freedom (free choices) but also on ability. If someone is unable to do otherwise, his action is not free and responsibility is lessened or even completely removed.22 It is in this sense that critics of determinism view responsibility. According to the indeterminist, if God has decreed every action that comes to pass then people cannot do otherwise, and if they could not have done otherwise (i.e., they lack the ability) then they should not be held responsible. This objection will be handed below in the discussion on ability.

In summary, responsibility has two senses. In the first sense, a person is completely responsible to God since he is under his supreme authority and is answerable to him for all his actions. In the second sense, responsibility is predicated on freedom and ability, i.e., responsibility is attributable when a person is liable for his actions. A person is thought not to be liable for his actions if he is unable to do otherwise and was therefore not acting freely. The nature of man’s ability and freedom (free will) must be considered to address how man can be liable for his actions.

Excursus on Ignorance

Before discussing the nature of man’s ability and freedom, a brief look at how ignorance affects responsibility assists in bringing light to the discussion. Ignorance factors into the tension between divine sovereignty and human responsibility in two ways. In the first way, some use ignorance to excuse man of responsibility. The objection is raised: if man is ignorant of God and his commands, how can man be held responsible for not obeying God?23 In the second way, ignorance can be used to support human responsibility in a deterministic world. If man is ignorant of God’s decree—and he is (Deut 29:29)—then man makes decisions apart from knowing what God has decreed. That is, because man is ignorant of God’s decree, the decree does not act as a constraint upon man’s decisions or actions. This leaves man responsible for his own decisions.

The first way ignorance is used (i.e., where ignorance excuses man) is an unbiblical idea. The objection that ignorance of God and his commands frees man of responsibility is addressed in Romans 1:19–20. Ignorance of God simply cannot be appealed to. God has made himself known in what he has created and in man himself who is created in the image of God (Gen 1:26–27). God has written his morality on man’s heart and his conscience also bears witness (Rom 2:15). Man is without excuse before God, i.e., an appeal to ignorance does not free man from responsibility since he does know God.24 In fact, ignorance is oftentimes willful, preferring it over knowledge, and results in increasing a person’s culpability. Suppressing the truth may or may not be a willful, but even in modern courts of law, “ignorance of the law is no excuse.”

Consider this illustration to support the second way (i.e., ignorance of God’s decree makes man responsible) ignorance is used. Suppose it is predetermined that Tom will be involved in minor car accident tomorrow. Tom is completely ignorant of this predetermined plan since, like all, Tom does not know the future or God’s decree. The following day, Tom sets out and drives his car to work like he does every day. Tom follows too closely to the car in front of him and, as he adjusts the radio, the car in front of him slows down. Tom is unable to react in time and his car collides into the car in front of him. In this case, Tom is fully responsible for his actions. He had no knowledge of God’s decree and therefore God’s decree did not influence his decision to follow too closely or to adjust the radio. As far as Tom was concerned, he acted completely autonomously and admits his responsibility. God’s decree is not an agent imposing itself on Tom against his will.

Therefore it is seen that ignorance cannot be used to excuse responsibility. Rather, from a human standpoint, ignorance of God’s decree leaves man responsible for his actions, even though they have been predetermined by God.

Ability

Like responsibility, ability must be discussed in more than one sense. For example, if someone is scheduled for a speaking engagement that conflicts with a previous appointment, it might be said that he can speak or that he cannot speak. He can speak in the sense that he is physically able to do it, but he cannot speak in the sense that he is speaking at a different event. Perhaps the speaker can make it to the event, but cannot speak due to severe illness.25 This small example demonstrates that there are many senses in which a person is able or unable to act. In terms of man’s ability, it can be said that man is unable to do a certain act if it is not part of God’s decree. Yet it can also be said that man is able in another sense. For example, people cannot come to faith in Christ unless God draws them (John 6:44), yet in a physical sense people can believe in Christ since they are rational beings created in the image of God and capable of faith. People who cannot come to God do not lack anything physically, but do lack spiritually—they have not been born again (John 3:3; 1 John 5:1).

Thus, a distinction can be made between (1) spiritual or moral ability and (2) natural or physical ability.26 In the first sense of ability, the Bible clearly teaches man’s spiritual and moral inability. In the second sense, man has natural and physical abilities. There is nothing physical that makes him unable to submit to Christ’s lordship. Therefore, people are held fully responsible since they are physically or naturally able to seek God. No one is keeping the unbeliever by force so that he is unable to come to Christ. If the unbeliever does not come to Christ then he has only himself to blame since in his natural ability, he never desired to seek God.27

One example that demonstrates this distinction of ability is the crucifixion. The Jewish leaders, Pontius Pilot, Herod, and others involved were doing exactly what God had ordained (Acts 2:23; 4:27–28). In this sense, they were unable to do otherwise since no creature can thwart God’s plans (Isa 14:27; Job 42:1–2). Speaking of ability in a physical or natural sense, those involved in the crucifixion were not forced or unable to do otherwise. They had no knowledge of the secret decree of God and were acting according to their own desires and not by coercion from God.
Another example that demonstrates the relationship of differing kinds of ability and responsibility is as follows. Suppose Tom wakes up in his home and decides to stay in his bedroom for the entire day. Unbeknownst to Tom, his bedroom door has been barred from the outside so that he is unable to leave his room. In this case, Tom is not able to leave his room, but he had no desire to leave. In this scenario Tom is responsible for staying in his own room even though he was unable to leave. Tom acted according to his free choice, even though it was predetermined that he would not leave his room. Some people may object, saying Tom was not free since he was unable to choose to leave. This provides a segue into the discussion on freedom and the nature of free will.

Free Will

The Bible clearly teaches that man has free will (Josh 24:15), but it does not state the nature of the free will that man possesses. Philosophers continue to argue over the nature of human free will. Free will is typically assumed by indeterminists to be the ability to choose the contrary.28 This freedom to do otherwise is also called contra-causal freedom or libertarian freedom.29 It must be recognized that this type of freedom is logically contradictory with the biblical teaching on divine sovereignty where God has ordained all things with certainty.30 Also in the contra-causal freedom system it must follow that God has a lesser freedom than man since he cannot choose to do evil, yet man can. It also follows that if man has the freedom to do otherwise, then God’s freedom must somehow be subservient. In other words, if God cannot impose himself on man’s contra-causal freedom, but instead must respond to man’s free choices, then God becomes significantly less free than his creation. Such a view must be recognized as unscriptural. Does not the potter have power over the clay (Isa 29:16; Rom 9:21)? In addition, contra-causal freedom must also be rejected in the eternal state. In the eternal state sin will be no more—there will be no possible way to choose evil rather than good.31 If humans in the eternal state are free creatures and are unable to sin then either they lack the contra-causal freedom they enjoyed in this world, or are in a sense limited in that they cannot choose contrary when the contrary would involve sin. The true nature of human freedom must be reconciled with determinism, both in this present world and in the eternal state. Contra-causal freedom is incompatible with both, and therefore, is not an option.

Like responsibility and ability, freedom entails a number of senses that must be considered. First, unlike the proponents of contra-causal or libertarian freedom, the biblical witness is clear that mankind is in bondage and is not free. Man is in bondage to sin and does not have the freedom to do what is good (Rom 8:7; 6:15–23; John 8:34; 2 Cor 3:17). Christ is the one who is able to set man free from this bondage (John 8:34–36). This is the most important kind of freedom that is mentioned in Scripture—the freedom from sin given to man by the work of Christ.32 That man is in bondage to sin and not free to do good does not remove the fact that he is a creature subject to moral evaluation from God. Being subject to moral evaluation (i.e., answerable) to God makes humans morally responsible.

Second, if the deterministic viewpoint defended above is correct, how can a human be free if his actions are determined? And if humans are not free, how can they be morally responsible? It is argued here that there is a true sense of human freedom despite their actions being causally determined. Causes can be categorized as constraining and non-constraining causes. A constraining cause would force a person to act against their will, whereas a non-constraining cause would ensure the resulting act but would do so in accordance with the person’s will or desires.

The preeminent example of a non-constraining but causally determined action would be the crucifixion as recounted in Acts 2:23 and Acts 4:27–28. Those who were responsible to crucify Jesus did so in accordance with their desires, yet it was an event predetermined by God to occur. In this case, those who crucified Jesus were not constrained against their will, and so, they acted freely.33 At the same time God predetermined the events to occur just as they did. But, how could God predetermine that the crucifixion would take place by the willing actions of those involved? The answer is that God not only ordained the ends, but also the means to the ends. God ordained all the necessary influences and circumstances necessary for those involved to act without constraint so that they did exactly what they desired to do and they did exactly what God determined that they should do.34

Therefore, freedom in this sense—man chooses according to his desires—does not logically contradict determinism, but is compatible with it. For this reason it is commonly called “compatibilism.”35 Frame defines compatibilistic freedom as “the freedom to do what you want to do.”36 People behave according to the desires of their heart (Prov 4:23; Luke 6:45; Matt 7:15–20; 12:33–35; Mark 7:21–22). When people do not behave according to their desires, they are either acting irrationally or they are being forced against their will by some external constraint. According to this understanding, even if every act a person ever performs is caused by something or someone else, that person is still free when he chooses to act according to his desires.

To illustrate, suppose Tom must choose between hot chocolate and coffee. Tom is free to choose either. Even though Tom is free, the outcome is determined because Tom dislikes coffee so much that he would never take it. There are sufficient causes in Tom’s past which have shaped his desires or reasons for disliking coffee. There is always a reason or cause that determines what man will choose. However, as has been argued, this does not mean that man is not free to act according to his desires.

The Will, the Heart, and the Determinant of Choice

The human will and the human heart must be distinguished when discussing how free choice is exercised. As noted briefly above, the heart is the source of desires (Prov 4:23) and “the will is the faculty of choice, the immediate cause of all action.”37 Choice is the acceptance of one thing and the refusal of alternatives. The will is not the ultimate cause of choice since there must be something which influences the choice, i.e., which determines the choice. Something causes the will to choose; therefore the will is not the causative agent. If there is indifference between choices, then no choice will be made. As soon as some kind of preference appears, indifference goes away and the choice is made.38

To summarize, what has been argued is that free choice is compatible with the fact that God causes all things. Under God’s sovereignty man still has freedom and acts freely in accordance with his nature and natural desires. Since man is free to act according to his desires, man is responsible for his actions.39

God’s Decree

The nature of God’s decree requires a brief clarification.40 God has decreed all that was, is, and is to come (Isa 46:9–10; Eph 1:11). Every human action has been predetermined by God, even the outcome of the roll of the dice (Prov 16:33). God’s decree is his efficacious plan that cannot be thwarted (Job 42:2; Ps 135:6). God’s decree is based on his desires and purposes, so it is only God who is independently free. This, however, does not make man a marionette where God’s decree acts to pull the strings. As a plan, it is not a force or an agent acting in the world to ensure its success. God’s plan does not cause anything to happen. Feinberg states, “While one person’s actions might cause another to act, or a storm might cause a flood, the decree isn’t something that acts or happens in our world, but rather the blueprint for whatever occurs.”41 There may be a sense in which God’s decree can be thought of as the ultimate or remote cause of all things, but it is God, angels, human beings, and other agents that have actual (immediate) causative power. There is a necessary distinction between the plan and the working out of the plan. This is important when discussing responsibility since, as causative agents, humanity is still responsible for their actions as they carry out the predetermined plan of God.42

A Case for Human Responsibility

As seen in the discussion so far, many factors affect the nature of human responsibility. It is important to remember that as a creature, man is answerable to his creator. In this way, mankind is completely responsible to God, the judge of all intents and actions. This is the primary sense in which man is responsible. The second sense of responsibility, defined in terms of liability, does not have as short an answer. First, humans are liable for actions that are done compatibilistically free. Humans act according to their desires and when they do so, they are culpable for their actions—even though they are sovereignly predetermined. What about actions that people commit because they were forced to do them against their wishes? It may seem natural that man should not at all be held responsible in such cases, but in such cases responsibility may be lessened, but not necessarily removed.43

As an example, consider the scenario where Tom is held at gunpoint and told to hand over his money. Tom chooses to comply and hand over his money. The money that Tom was carrying was not his own, but money raised for charity and he was on his way to deposit it. Is Tom responsible for handing over the charity money? The likely response is “Not at all.” But the fact remains that Tom still willingly handed over the money. He still made the choice to hand over the money, even though his choice was influenced by a threat on his life. Perhaps if Tom refused the assailant would have fled. Perhaps if Tom took precautions in transporting the money this could have been prevented. An endless number of factors are involved, and while Tom’s degree of culpability in the act is low, it cannot be completely removed unless he is physically forced with his will never conceding to the action. While contrived, the point this example intends to illustrate is that man is rarely free of culpability.

As God does not force man in such a way that man cannot act according to his desires, man is culpable (liable) for his actions.44 The majority of man’s actions are not coerced as the example above, but are free actions according to his own desires and so he is held fully accountable for those actions. When acting under coercion man is likely still partially accountable for his actions. Therefore, whether responsibility is taken in terms of answering to a higher authority or responsibility is taken in terms of liability, both senses make man responsible. Man is responsible to his creator because he has authority over him and man is liable for his actions since they are compatibilistically free according to his desires.

Divine Responsibility

The discussion to this point has been focused on human responsibility. An arguably more challenging problem involves God and his responsibility for sin. While the focus of this paper is on human responsibility, a brief discussion on the responsibility of God helps to complete the picture of responsibility in a deterministic world.

If God has decreed all that will take place from eternity past—including sin—how is God not responsible for sin? It must first be recognized that from the discussion of responsibility above, God is not responsible in the sense that he is not answerable to a higher authority. God answers to no one and so is not responsible to anyone or anything (except himself). There is no higher authority that is able to judge the actions of God. God is the definition and determiner of what is right.45 Concerning responsibility in the second sense (i.e., liability), how is God not liable for sin since he decreed it? It necessarily depends on why God would decree sin, i.e., on the intent of the decree. Also, if God has decreed all that will take place and does no wrong himself, how does he ensure his plan is carried out when it involves so much wickedness? Before looking further at these questions, providence and concurrence must be discussed.

Providence and Concurrence

Providence is the efficacious administration of the things decreed by God.46 In order to understand how God administrates his creation, a number of solutions rely on the distinction between primary and secondary causes, but such explanations must avoid two problems. First, if God is directly involved in all secondary causes then the world ends up being pantheistic, where God is in all and is the immediate agent of the causal system.47 Second, if God being the primary cause has initiated a series of mechanistic secondary causes then God becomes quasi-deistic.48 Both of these pitfalls portray a God foreign to Scripture. Avoiding these errors lead to a vague definition of concurrence: “The cooperation of the divine power with all subordinate powers, according to the pre-established laws of their operation, causing them to act and to act precisely as they do.”49 This vagueness is a result of the inability to articulate how God can govern the universe with certainty in terms of causation and not err into pantheism or deism.50 What is important to note and what is argued in this paper is that God’s action remains sufficiently indirect to preserve genuine human responsibility.

Mavrodes objects to this notion and sees God’s governing of the universe in this sense to make God responsible for sin. He states, “It implies, so it seems to me, that when a child is raped, then God is the rapist of that child. Of course, His rape of the child is mediate, and there is a human rapist who is the immediate agent of that deed. But the truth, according to this view, is that God (along with the human agent) is also a genuine doer of that deed.”51 Essentially Mavrodes objection leads to the problem of evil which is beyond the scope of this paper.52 However, this paper will briefly respond to the objection.

God’s purpose in creating the present world is wholly righteous and serves his purpose of bringing glory to himself. In this world God desired to create the kind of humans that man is—rational, personal creatures with (compatibilistically) free will. God also created the natural order and natural laws to suit his purposes. God does not alter those natural laws if something bad is going to happen (such as the rape of a child). If God intervened and prevented a person from raping a child (by miraculously stopping them physically or miraculously constraining their will) then his purpose to create creatures like he did is not fulfilled. God has not purposed and is not obligated to stop such evils before they happen. God is not obligated since he answers to no higher authority and God is not liable since he does not constrain the will of the evil doer to do evil (Jas 1:13). In this way, God is not responsible for the sinful acts of men but has included those acts in his plan to serve his good purpose.

Harmonizing Divine Sovereignty, Sin, and Moral Responsibility

How does God receive praise for the good man does, but avoid the responsibility for evil that man commits? Man by nature desires sin and in his natural state cannot please God (Rom 8:8).53 Man in his own power cannot do anything that is good (Rom 3:10–12; Ps 14:1–3; 53:1–4). Therefore, if man is to do something good in God’s eyes, then man must be enabled and empowered by God to do so. In this way, God can be praised for any good that man accomplishes.54 It can be said that in Philippians 2:12–13 man is the proximate cause in working out his own salvation, and God is the remote cause doing the enabling and empowering. The same can be said about the inspiration of Scripture, man is the proximate cause and God is the remote cause moving the writers to pen holy writ (1 Pet 1:21). In these cases God is responsible for these good things because his own action is necessary to overcome the inability of man to do these good things.

In a similar way, God cannot be held responsible for the evil that man does. Man’s actions are (compatibilistically) free and, unlike any good deed, God does not need to act so that man does evil. Man’s ability to sin is part of his nature. God does not need to enable man to sin. As for God’s role in sin, Scripture is very clear. God cannot do evil, and cannot be tempted with evil himself (Jas 1:13). According to the Scriptures, man is tempted to do evil because of his own desires (Jas 1:14). Temptations to sin arise during circumstances in daily living (e.g., going to work, to school, shopping).55 These usual circumstances are themselves morally neutral, so if God ordains them to be in people’s lives then no culpability for their being tempted in those circumstances can be ascribed to God. The temptation to sin in these circumstances does not come from God, but comes from man’s own desires. As to the proximate cause, people are clearly the actors, not God. Even as a remote cause, God’s involvement is bringing about the circumstances in which man is tempted, not for the pleasure of seeing his creatures sin, but for his good purpose.56

As a final question: is God responsible for not enabling and empowering every man to overcome sin? God is not responsible since he is not required to enable and empower every man to overcome sin. The enablement and empowerment that comes from God to man is an act of his grace. Grace by definition is unmerited and ill deserved favor. God is not obligated to give grace, since if he was, grace would be no more grace. Man does not deserve or merit favor from God, therefore, God cannot be held responsible should he choose to withhold it to serve his higher purpose.

Conclusion

The complex relationship between divine sovereignty and human responsibility necessitates a multi-faceted solution. Responsibility, freedom, ability, and the nature and outworking of God’s decree must all be properly understood and grounded in biblical truth in order to understand how mankind is held responsible for sin in a world predetermined by God. While the solution presented above may not explain exactly how God works all things according to the counsel of his will, it does demonstrate why man is responsible for his actions. God decrees all that comes to pass for his own glory. This includes justly punishing the wicked and redeeming unworthy sinners. He is to be praised for both acts. Humanity is responsible to submit to this great God.

  1. Some theologians say the two concepts are taught in Scripture but are irreconcilable. They maintain that it is not a logical contradiction, but the two truths must remain in “tension” (D. A. Carson, Divine Sovereignty and Human Responsibility: Biblical Perspectives in Tension [Atlanta: John Knox Press, 1981]) or are an antinomy—which is defined to be an apparent contradiction (J. I Packer, Evangelism & The Sovereignty of God [Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1991]). Carson states, “I claim only that, with a certain amount of care, logical pitfalls may be avoided, so that belief in divine sovereignty and in human responsibility does not entail logical contradiction” (Divine Sovereignty and Human Responsibility, p. 206.).
  2. All Scripture is from the English Standard Version unless otherwise specified.
  3. Choosing sin freely in a world where God predetermines all things may seem like a contradictory statement. However, this paper seeks to prove that the freedom man possesses is not contradictory to determinism.
  4. For the free-will defense see Alvin Plantinga, God, Freedom, and Evil (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1977). For a more current and popular treatment see Norman L Geisler, If God, Why Evil?: A New Way to Think About the Question (Bloomington, MN: Bethany House, 2011). For an example of the middle-knowledge theory see William Lane Craig, The Only Wise God: The Compatibility of Divine Foreknowledge and Human Freedom (Grand Rapids: Baker, 1987). Both of these systems are common defenses in Arminian-leaning theological systems. These philosophically constructed arguments are excluded since each limit God’s sovereignty in a way that does not agree with the biblical evidence.
  5. Normal Geisler defines true freedom (i.e., contra-causal or libertarian freedom) as “the power to do otherwise” (If God, Why Evil, p. 30). The Bible never ascribes this kind of freedom to man. Man is unable to thwart God’s predetermined plan. A complete discussion on this concept occurs later in this paper.
  6. William Lane Craig says, “The counterfactuals of creaturely freedom which confront Him are outside His control. He has to play with the hand He has been dealt” (“Question 239: Molinism and the Soteriological Problem of Evil Once More,” par. 22, http://www.reasonablefaith.org/site/ News2?page=NewsArticle &id=9193 [accessed 14 December 2011]).
  7. This notion of contra-causal freedom is the basis on which advocates argue that humanity is responsible for their sin. However, God becomes contingent or dependent—a divine counter-puncher reacting to his “free” creatures.
  8. Many more passages demonstrating the independence and freedom of God are discussed in the section on Determinism.
  9. Arthur W Pink, The Sovereignty of God (Grand Rapids: Baker, 1930), p. 178.
  10. For sake of brevity and clarity every concept relating to the topic of divine sovereignty and human responsibility is not discussed here. For example, some argue that the relationship between time and eternity factor into the answer of the sovereignty-responsibility tension, but this ends up trying to explain the current problem by an even more obscure one. Definitions presented are the ones salient to the argument of this paper.
  11. Richard Taylor, “Determinism,” in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Paul Edwards (New York: Macmillan, 1967), 2:359, quoted in John Feinberg, “God Ordains All Things,” in Predestination & Free Will: Four Views of Divine Sovereignty & Human Freedom, ed. David Basinger and Randall Basinger (Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 1986), p. 21. Feinberg provides his own definition: “For every action or event which is causally determined, there is a state of affairs just prior to its occurrence which, when combined with some causal laws, makes it certain the event or action will occur.” Frame defines it as “the view that every event (including human actions) has a sufficient cause other than itself” (John M. Frame, The Doctrine of God: A Theology of Lordship [Phillipsburg, NJ: P & R, 2002], p. 136).
  12. Feinberg, “God Ordains All Things,” p. 20. This does not mean that indeterminists believe that choices are random. There are reasons for every choice, but there is no necessary causal explanation of why the person acted according to one reason over another.
  13. cf. Isa 10:5–17; 14:27; 37:26; 41:21–23; 46:11; 64:8; Ps 33:8–11; 135:6; 139:16; Prov 21:1; Dan 4:34–35; Jer 18:4–6; 1 Cor 1:26–31; Eph 1:11
  14. Feinberg, “God Ordains All Things,” p. 23.
  15. Frame has a lengthy discussion on the issue (The Doctrine of God, pp. 146–47). His response is summarized here.
  16. Anthony Flew, ed., A Dictionary of Philosophy, Revised Second Edition. (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1984), p. 306.
  17. See fuller discussion in Frame, The Doctrine of God, pp. 119–25.
  18. The Bible also affirms that humans are responsible to seek salvation, to receive Christ, to repent, believe and be baptized (2 Thess 1:8–9; Acts 2:38). The Bible affirms that man is responsible if he stays in his unbelief (John 3:18). But doesn’t God create man with a sinful nature that makes these things impossible? The Bible recognizes man’s sinful nature and teaches that mankind has received this natural sinfulness because of Adam’s sin (Rom 5:19). And regardless of his sinful nature acquired from Adam, the Bible is clear that man is answerable to God and responsible for the sinful acts he commits. The blame for man’s sinful nature cannot be placed on God, but is placed on Adam. Later in this paper the issue of God’s responsibility for man’s sin is discussed further. That discussion is applicable here in addressing the cause of man’s sinful nature.
  19. James R. White, The Potter’s Freedom: A Defense of the Reformation and a Rebuttal to Norman Geisler’s Chosen But Free (Amityville, NY: Calvary Press Publishing, 2009), p. 331.
  20. Flew defines two principle conditions that are necessary for responsibility: (1) that the agent knows what he is doing, and (2) that his desires and intentions play some role in the act or failure to act (A Dictionary of Philosophy, p. 306).
  21. Frame recognizes these distinctions of responsibility as (1) accountability to a higher authority, and (2) liability for the consequences of man’s actions (The Doctrine of God, p. 119).
  22. Other factors such as ignorance, sanity, legal or illicit drugs factor into what a person is able to do, and therefore, to what degree a person is responsible.
  23. John 5:22 (“If I had not come and spoken to them, they would not have been guilty of sin, but now they have no excuse for their sin”) seems, at first, to lend support to this objection. But John 5:22 does not speak of all sin, but the specific sin of rejecting Christ (his words and his miracles). Romans 3:9–10 plainly states that all are under sin, even those who were not exposed to Christ’s ministry. This is similar to the common objection: “What about people who have never heard?” The implicit assumption in this objection is that people who have never heard are innocent and not responsible for not seeking God and believing in Jesus Christ. Romans 1:19–20 demonstrates that this assumption is invalid. “For what can be known about God is plain to them, because God has shown it to them. For his invisible attributes, namely, his eternal power and divine nature, have been clearly perceived, ever since the creation of the world, in the things that have been made. So they are without excuse.”
  24. A further objection is usually offered which asks: What of the mentally handicapped or infants who do not have the mental capacity to comprehend? In response, this case is not explicitly handled in Scripture. For the mentally handicapped and infants it is granted that ignorance may lessen their responsibility, but not necessarily remove it. If the responsibility of these individuals is not absolved, would they not all end up in hell? It must be recalled that in salvation God is the author, not man. God is free to save whoever he wishes to save.
  25. Example is a condensed version taken from Frame, The Doctrine of God, pp. 131–32.
  26. Jonathan Edwards argues for this distinction when he asserts that fallen man has the natural ability to choose God but lacks the moral ability to do so (Jonathan Edwards, Freedom of the Will, ed. Paul Ramsey [New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1957], pp. 156–62). A.W. Pink says, “By nature [man] possesses natural ability but lacks moral and spiritual ability. The fact that he does not possess the latter does not destroy his responsibility, because his responsibility rests upon the fact that he does possess the former” (The Sovereignty of God, p. 191).
  27. Frame (The Doctrine of God, pp. 132–33) examines the possibility of Jesus’ bones being broken. Jesus’ bones were prevented from being broken to fulfill prophecy (John 19:36), but in the physical sense his bones were able to be broken since they were human bones. So in differing respects the breaking of Jesus’ bones was physically possible, but impossible by virtue of God’s decree.
  28. Normal Geisler defines true freedom as “the power to do otherwise” (If God, Why Evil, p. 30). William Lane Craig doesn’t define what human freedom is, but his use of the term “genuine freedom” seems to assume the ability to choose the contrary. According to Craig, genuine freedom is non-fatalistic and also non-causally determined (The Only Wise God, pp. 13–17). This makes his view of freedom incompatible with causal determinism.
  29. For an excellent critique of libertarianism, see Frame, The Doctrine of God, pp. 137–45.
  30. See Carson, Divine Sovereignty and Human Responsibility, pp. 206–9. Also see discussion in this paper on Determinism which demonstrates that God’s sovereignty equates to determinism.
  31. Geisler calls God’s freedom “absolute freedom” since he “has the freedom not to choose evil” (If God, Why Evil, p. 30). He claims the saints in heaven have this type of freedom relatively. Inconsistency is demonstrated as his theodicy rests on giving humans a true freedom—a freedom that includes the possibility of sin. Such freedom is argued to be necessary to truly love God freely. He offers no further explanation of this “relative” freedom or an attempt to reconcile the logical contradiction. He simply asserts that here on earth people must have the ability to choose evil or else people are simply robots. Why then would people not be robots in heaven since they lack the ability to sin?
  32. Frame, The Doctrine of God, p. 135.
  33. This does not deny the existence of any constraining causes. If a person is forced to act against their desires then such an action would be a result of constraining causes. In this case and according to the definitions argued here, the person’s action would not be considered free.
  34. Geisler sees this as reprehensible (If God, Why Evil, p. 31). He argues that if God gives men the desire to sin, how are they free? He bases his objection in his assertion that God wants all to do good. First, Geisler’s assertion that God wants all to do good is false. In the crucifixion men committed evil in accordance with God’s predetermined plan (cf. Acts 2:23; 4:27–28). God’s predetermined intent was not evil, but it did involve and was achieved by evil men. Second, the men who crucified Christ are free in the sense that they did what they desired to do and were not forced against their will. God did not have to act or coerce them to crucify the Lord.
  35. Feinberg, “God Ordains All Things,” p. 24. Compatibilism is freedom defined in such a way that is compatible with causal determinism.
  36. Frame, The Doctrine of God, p. 136.
  37. Pink, The Sovereignty of God, p. 161.
  38. See Ibid., pp. 161–66. John Murray also has an excellent treatment demonstrating that volition is determined by the inward disposition (John Murray, “Free Agency,” in Collected Writings of John Murray [Carlisle, PA: Banner of Truth, 1976], 2: 60–66).
  39. Calvin argued the same way and understood guilt to be established if an act was done voluntarily—irrespective of whether the sinner could have avoided the act (Concerning the Eternal Predestination of God, trans. J. K. Reid [Westminster/John Knox, 1997], pp. 122–23).
  40. See John Feinberg, No One Like Him: The Doctrine of God (Wheaton, IL: Crossway, 2001), pp. 515–19. Feinberg discusses six principles of the nature of God’s decree: (1) the decree is founded in God’s wisdom; (2) the decree is eternal; (3) the decree has the ultimate purpose of bringing God glory; (4) the decree is efficacious; (5) the decree is all-comprehensive; and (6) the decree is based on God’s desires and purposes and so is free.
  41. Ibid., p. 530.
  42. How God’s decree is carried out (providence/primary and secondary causation/concurrence) will be discussed below in the discussion on Divine Responsibility.
  43. It is important to remember that responsibility as liability is measured in degrees.
  44. The exception being in salvation where God gloriously regenerates the heart of sinful man. Creating new desires to do what is good and acceptable in the sight of God. God does not do anything similar in the lives of the natural man to force him to desire evil.
  45. God is holy (1 Pet 1:15; Lev 11:44); God is perfect (Matt 5:48); God is light (1 John 1:5); God is love (1 John 4:8, 16); God is righteous (1 John 2:29); God is good (Ps 118:29); God is merciful, gracious, kind and true (Ps 116:5; Exod 34:5–7).
  46. Louis Berkhof, Systematic Theology (Carlisle, PA: Banner of Truth, 1958), p. 165.
  47. Pantheism regards the universe as a manifestation of God. God is the universe.
  48. Deism regards God as the creator but he does not interfere with his creation. God has “wound up” the universe and is letting it run its course.
  49. Berkhof, Systematic Theology, p. 171.
  50. Berkouwer says, “We cannot explain the sequences of history with an all-devouring system of causation, nor by a theory of divine flux. The Scriptures show us God’s work” (The Providence of God [Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1952], p. 153)
  51. George Mavrodes, “A Reply to Professors Feinberg and Pinnock,” Christian Scholar’s Review 16 (July 1987): 403.
  52. Feinberg treats the subject exhaustively in The Many Faces of Evil: Theological Systems and the Problems of Evil, Revised and expanded ed. (Wheaton, IL: Crossway, 2004).
  53. This nature state is a result of Adam’s sin. See fn. 19.
  54. See Feinberg, No One Like Him, pp. 653–54.
  55. Even while listening to a sermon someone can become wrongfully angered at what is being said or entertain lustful thoughts about someone sitting nearby.
  56. See Feinberg, No One Like Him, pp. 653–54.